7 FEBRUARY 1941, Page 9

EVIL AND GOD

By C. S. LEWIS

R. JOAD'S article on " God and Evil " last week sug- gests the interesting conclusion that since neither mechanism " nor " emergent evolution " will hold water, we ust choose in the long run between some monotheistic philo- phy, like the Christian, and some such dualism as that the Zoroastrians. I agree with Dr. Joad in rejecting schanism and emergent evolution. Mechanism, like all terialist systems, bieaks down at the problem of knowledge. thought is the undesigned and irrelevant product of cerebral otions, what reason have we to trust it? As for emergent olution, if anyone insists on using the word God to mean whatever the universe happens to be going to do next," of urse we 'cannot prevent him. But nobody would in fact use it unless he had a secret belief that what is coming t will be an improvement. Such a belief, besides being warranted, presents peculiar difficulties to an emergent olutionist. If things can improve, this means that there st be some absolute standard of good above and outside the smic process to which that process can approximate. There no sense in talking of " becoming better " if better means ply " what we are becoming "—it is like congratulating urself on reaching your destination and defining destination " the place you have reached." Mellontolatry, or the rship of the future, is a fuddled religion.

We are left then to choose between monotheism and dualism between a single good almighty source of being, and two ml, uncreated, antagonistic Powers, one good and the other d. Dr. Joad suggests that the latter view stands to 'n from the " new urgency " of the fact of evil. But what urgency? Evil may seem more urgent to us than it did the Victorian philosophers—favoured members of the ppiest class in the happiest country of the world at the rld's happiest period. But it is no more urgent for us than the great majority of monotheists all down the ages. The ssic expositions of the doctrine that the world's miseries are mpatible with its creation and guidance by a wholly good g come from Boethius waiting in prison to be beaten to th and from St. Augustine meditating on the sack of Rome.

e present state of the world is normal ; it was the last century was the abnormality.

This drives us to ask why so many generations rejected lism. Not, assuredly, because they were unfamiliar with ering ; and not because its obvious prima fade plausibility ped them. It is more likely that they saw its two fatal culties, the one metaphysical, and the other moral.

The metaphysical difficulty is this. The two Powers, the and the evil, do not explain each other. Neither Ormuzd Ahriman can claim to be the Ultimate. More ultimate either of them is the inexplicable fact of their being re together. Neither of them chose this tete-a-tete. Each them, therefore, is conditioned—finds himself willy-nilly in situation ; and either that situation itself, or some unknown ce which sm has not yet reached the ground of being. You cannot t two conditioned and mutually independent beings as produced that situation, is the real Ultimate. the self-grounded, self-comprehending Absolute. On the level of picture-thinking this difficulty is symbolised by our inability to think of Ormuzd and Ahriman without smuggling in the idea of a common space in which they can be together and thus confessing that we are not yet dealing with the source of the universe but only with two members contained in it. Dualism is a truncated metaphysic.

The moral difficulty is that Dualism gives evil a positive, substantive, self-consistent nature, like that of good. If this were true, if Ahriman existed in his own right no less than Crmuzd, what could we mean - by calling Ormuzd good except that we happened to prefer him? Those wi.o serve Ahriman happen to prefer him. In what sense can the one party be said to be right and the other wrong? If evil has the same kind of reality as good, the same autonomy and completeness, our allegiance to good becomes the arbitrarily chosen loyalty of a partisan. A sound theory of value demands something very different. It demands that good should be original and evil a mere perversion ; that good should be the tree and evil the ivy ; the,• good should be able to see all round evil (as when sane men understand lunacy) while evil cannot retaliate in kind; that good should be able to exist on its own while evil requires the good on which it is parasitic in order to continue its parasitic existence.

The consequences of • neglecting this are serious. It means believing that bad men like badness as such, in the same way in which good men like goodness. At first this denial of any common nature between us and our enemies seems gratifying. We call them fiends and feel that we need not forgive them. But, in reality, along with the power to forgive, we have lost the power to condemn. If a taste for cruelty and a taste for kindness were equally ultimate and basic, by what common standard could the one reprove the other? In reality cruelty does not come from desiring evil as such, but from perverted sexuality, inordinate resentment, or lawless ambition and avarice. That is precisely why it can be judged and con- demned from the standpoint of innocent sexuality, righteous anger, and ordinate acquisitiveness. The master can correct a boy's sums because they are blunders in arithmetic—in the same arithmetic which he also does and does better. If they were not even attempts at arithmetic—if they were not in the arithmetical world at all—they could not be arithmetical mistakes.

Good and evil, then, are not on all fours. Badness is not even bad in the same way in which goodness is good. Ormuzd and Ahriman cannot be equals. In the long run, Ormuzd must be original and Ahriman derivative. The first hazy idea of devil must, if we begin to think, be analysed into the more precise ideas of " fallen " and " rebel " angel. But only in the long run. Christianity can go much further with the Dualist than Dr. Joad's article seems to suggest. There was never any question of tracing all evil to man ; in fact, the New Testament has a good deal more to say about dark superhuman powers than about the fall of Adam. As far as this world is con- cerned, a Christian can share most of the Zoroastrian outlook ; we all live between the " fell, incensed points" of Michael and Satan. The difference between the Christian and the Dualist is that the Christian thinks one stage further and sees that if Michael is really in the right and Satan really in the wrong this must mean that they stand in two different relations to somebody or something far further back, to the ultimate ground of reality itself. All this, of course, has been watered down in modern times by the theologians who are afraid of " mythology", but those who are prepared to reinstate Ormuzd and Ahriman are presumably not squeamish on that score, Dualism can be a manly creed. In the Norse form ("The giants will beat the gods in the end, but I am on the side of the gods ") it is nobler by many degrees than most philoso- phies of the moment. But it is only a half-way house. Think- ing along these lines you can avoid Monotheism, and remain a Dualist, only by refusing to follow your thoughts home. To revive Dualism would be a real step backwards and a bad omen (though not the worst possible) for civilisation.